Assertion,
Knowledge, and Invariant Standards
William S. Larkin
Epistemic contextualism is the view that the
truth-conditions for knowledge attributions can vary across contexts as a
result of shifting epistemic standards.
According to Keith DeRose, the “chief bugaboo of contextualism has been
the concern that the contextualist is mistaking variability in the conditions
of warranted assertibility of knowledge attributions for a variability in their
truth conditions” (167).[1] In “Assertion, Knowledge, and Context,”
Keith DeRose attempts to hoist the proponents of this type of warranted
assertibility objection on their own petard. His strategy is to use the independently motivated idea that
warranted assertion requires knowledge to show that the variable conditions of
warranted assertibility to which proponents of the warranted assertibility
objection are committed actually imply epistemic contextualism. I will argue that DeRose’s attempt to use
the knowledge account of assertion to defuse the warranted assertibility
objection to contextualism fails, and for a reason that poses a general
challenge for the contextualist. For
there is a warranted assertibility maneuver to be made against the whole range
of the contextualists’ most compelling cases that is effective and that remains
unscathed by the argument from the knowledge account of assertion.
1.
Contextualist Cases
The primary motivation for contextualism has been to
provide a satisfying response to philosophical skepticism; but the primary
support for contextualism needs to come from, as DeRose says, “how ‘knows’ and
its cognates are utilized in non-philosophical conversation” (168). The contextualist needs to produce a pair of
ordinary conversational contexts where a sentence of the form ‘S knows that P’
is true in one but false in the other, though there is no difference in the
truth of P or the strength of S’s epistemic relation to P—i.e., S’s
evidence for and/or reliability concerning P.[2]
Adequate support for contextualism requires an intuitively compelling pair of
cases in which the quality of a subject S’s epistemic relation to a proposition
is sufficient for knowledge in one case but not the other. As DeRose puts it:
Following Austin’s lead, the
contextualist will appeal to pairs of cases that forcefully display this
variability: “Low standards” cases in which a speaker seems quite appropriately
and truthfully to ascribe knowledge to a subject will be paired with “high
standards” cases in which another speaker in a quite different and more demanding
context seems with equal propriety and truth to say that the same subject (or a
similarly positioned subject) does not know.
(169)
Consider DeRose’s Bank
Cases.[3] In these cases a subject S claims to know
that the bank is open on Saturday morning.
This proposition is in fact true and S’s belief is based on the ‘quite
solid grounds’ that S was at the bank two weeks ago and found that it was open
until noon on Saturdays. In the first
case—Low Bank—S and his wife are deciding whether to deposit their paychecks
on Friday or wait until Saturday morning, “where no disaster will ensue if
(they) waste a trip to the bank on Saturday only to find it closed” (170). In the second case—High Bank—“disaster,
not just disappointment, would ensue if (they) waited until Saturday only to
find (they) were too late” (170). In Low Bank it does not seem
reasonable to question the adequacy of the available evidence or require that
one go to further lengths to determine whether the bank has changed its hours
over the last couple of weeks. But in
High Bank, it does seem reasonable to question the adequacy of the available
evidence and require further efforts to make sure that the bank has not changed
its hours. In Low Bank almost everyone would say that S
does know that the bank is open on Saturday; but in High Bank almost everyone
would say that S does not know that the bank is open on Saturday. So here we have a pair of cases where it
seems that the truth conditions for a knowledge attribution, ‘S knows that the
bank is open on Saturday mornings’, vary across contexts without a change in
the subject’s epistemic relation to the relevant proposition.
The epistemic contexualist
contends that the contextual sensitivity of knowledge attributions in such
cases is the result of the contextual variability of the standards for
knowledge. Given the relatively small
risk involved in Low Bank, the available evidence is adequate; but given that disaster
will ensue if S is mistaken in High Bank, the evidence that the bank was open
on Saturday morning two weeks ago is no longer adequate. According to the contextualist, such cases
as these show that as the practical stakes go up so do the standards for
knowledge. Thus a knowledge attribution
may be true in one context but false in another because rising epistemic
standards have rendered what was once an adequate epistemic relation to a
proposition inadequate.
The
warranted assertibility objection (WAO) to contextualism contends that
our intuition concerning at least one of the contextualist’s cases is in fact
mistaken. The proponent of a WAO then
attempts to explain that intuition away using a warranted assertibility
maneuver (WAM) designed to show that the relevant attribution merely seems
false because its assertion is not warranted.
There are two WAO strategies available: First, one can claim that S does
not really know that P in the purportedly low standards case and that ‘S
does not know that P’ merely seems false there because its assertion is
unwarranted. We can call this first strategy
a Cartesian WAO, since it would be the approach taken by one who favored
invariantly high epistemic standards.
Second, one can claim that S really does know that P in the
purportedly high standards case and that ‘S knows that P’ merely seems false
there because its assertion is unwarranted.
We can call this second strategy a Moorean WAO, since it would be
the approach taken by one who favored invariantly low epistemic standards.
I
aim to put forth a Moorean WAO that is effective against a whole range of the
contextualist’s most compelling cases.
I will argue that the attribution ‘S knows that P’ only seems false in
certain purportedly high standards cases because its assertion generates a
false implicature and is therefore unwarranted in that context. I will also show that my Moorean WAO is
immune to DeRose’s argument from the knowledge account of assertion, to which
we now turn.
2. The Argument from the Knowledge Account of
Assertion
The knowledge account of assertion (KAA)
claims that “one must know that P in order to be positioned well enough with
respect to P to assert it” (179).[4] DeRose argues that the independently
motivated KAA can be used to show that the variable conditions of warranted
assertibility presupposed by the WAO actually imply epistemic contextualism.
“One
of the most important recommendations” for KAA is that “it provides a nice
handling of the knowledge version of Moore’s paradox and other troubling
conclusions” (180). Moore noted that
there is something extremely odd about sincerely uttering sentences of the form
‘P, but I don’t know that P.’ The
contents of such claims are clearly not logically inconsistent—it is clearly
possible that P is true but that I do not know that it is. Yet there seems to be something like a
logical difficulty involved in asserting such sentences. Moore himself explained the oddity by
saying, “By asserting P positively, you imply, though you don’t assert,
that you know that P.”[5]
KAA explains why a sincere
assertion of P would imply, in the sense of pragmatically implicate,
that you know that P: There is a general conversational rule that states that
one should assert only what one is in a position to know. Given that rule as a background presupposition,
my sincere assertion of P generates the implicature that I know that P. So in the Moore-paradoxical utterance, ‘P,
but I don’t know that P’, I implicate something by asserting the first conjunct
that I immediately deny by asserting the second conjunct. This explanation does justice to the feeling
that there is some kind of inconsistency involved, even though the content of
the proposition does not involve a contradiction. There is an inconsistency between something pragmatically
implicated and something semantically asserted.
After providing this glimpse
at the independent motivation for KAA, DeRose continues as follows:
The knowledge account of
assertion provides a powerful argument for contextualism: If the standards for
when one is in a position to warrantedly assert that P are the same as those
that comprise the truth-conditions for “I know that P”, then if the former vary
with context, so do the latter. In
short: The knowledge account of assertion together with the context-sensitivity
of assertibility yields contextualism about knowledge. (187)
Moreover, DeRose claims that the proponents of the
WAO are in fact committed to the context-sensitivity of warranted
assertibility:
It is clear and
uncontroversial that knowledge attributions are in some way governed by
varying epistemic standards. What makes
contextualism controversial are warranted assertibility concerns—the worry that
these varying standards are only conditions for the warranted assertibility,
rather than the truth, of the attributions.
(187)
So, according to DeRose, even the opponents of
epistemic contextualism accept varying epistemic standards. Invariantists
oppose contextualists only in saying that the varying epistemic standards do
not affect the truth-conditions of knowledge attributions but only their
warranted assertibility conditions.
DeRose concludes, then, that KAA is lethal to invariantism because “it
turns against the invariantists the very context-sensitivity in warranted
assertability that they themselves habitually appeal to” (188).
The argument from KAA to
show that proponents of the WAO are after all committed to epistemic
contextualism looks like this:
P1: The standards for when
one is in a position to warrantedly assert that P are the same as those that
comprise the truth-conditions for “I know that P”.
[from KAA]
C1: So, if the standards for the warranted assertibility vary with
context, then the truth-conditions for knowledge attributions vary with
context. [from P1]
P2: The standards for warranted assertibility do vary with
context.
[from WAO]
C2: So the truth conditions for knowledge attributions vary with
context—i.e., epistemic contextualism is true.
[from C1 and P2]
In the next section I will reject P2 of this
argument by presenting a particular WAO that does not presuppose that the standards
for warranted assertibility vary with context—it accounts for context sensitivity
in warranted assertibility without varying standards of warranted
assertibility. It is neither clear nor
uncontroversial that knowledge attributions are in any way governed by varying
epistemic standards. But first let me
point out a significant problem with P1 of the above argument as well.
The
first premise claims on the basis of KAA that the conditions for warranted
assertibility are the same as the truth conditions for knowledge
attributions. However, KAA is committed
only to the claim that knowledge is necessary for warranted assertibility, not
that it is sufficient. Thus KAA does not
imply that the standards for warranted assertibility are the same as the
standards for knowledge; it implies only that the standards for warranted
assertibility are comprised, perhaps merely, in part by the standards
for knowledge. There may be other
necessary conditions for warranted assertibility. If so, the context-sensitivity of warranted assertibility may be
the result of the contextual variability of something other than the standards
for knowledge.
While
this point is devastating to DeRose’s argument as it stands, I will not pursue
it. First, there may be a more subtle argument
available from KAA to P1 of the above argument that shows that the context
sensitivity of warranted assertibility must come from the variability in the
truth conditions for knowledge attributions and not from some other condition
on warranted assertibility. But second,
there is a more interesting and more generally significant objection to be made
against P2 of the argument.
3. The High
Stakes WAM and the KAA
The most compelling contextualist cases crucially
rely on raising what is practically at stake for a certain subject S on the
truth of some proposition P.[6] I will argue that there is an effective WAO
to any such pair of cases that is in fact immune to DeRose’s argument from
KAA. In particular, I will propose and
defend a Moorean WAM that explains away the mistaken intuition that S does not
know that P in high stakes cases without presupposing that the standards for
warranted assertibility of knowledge attributions rise as we move from low
stakes to high stakes cases. I will
call my strategy the high stakes WAM.
Take a pair of cases L and H
where the assertion ‘S knows that P’ seems true in L but false in H because
what is at stake on the truth of P has been raised considerably from X in L to
Y in H. Any convincing pair of cases of
this form crucially involves that S is willing to stake X but not Y on her
epistemic relation to P. It is S’s
reluctance in H that tells us just how high the stakes are; and it is the
stakes being so high that makes it seem that S’s epistemic relation to P is not
adequate for knowledge in H, though it was adequate in L.
A
Moorean invariantist can object to any such pair of cases as follows: S really does know that P in H, assuming she
knows that P in L, since epistemic standards are invariantly low. The attribution ‘S knows that P’ merely
seems false in H because its assertion there is not warranted. For asserting that S knows that P in H
generates the implicature that S is willing to stake Y on her epistemic
relation to P. Since S is not so
willing, the implicature is false and the assertion is unwarranted.
I will explain in the next
section exactly how the false implicature is generated in H and defend the
effectiveness of the WAM just made. But
first let me explain why this high stakes WAM is not undermined by the argument
from KAA.
The contextualist needs to
show that the standards for knowledge vary across context. The argument from KAA, proceeding from the
claim that the standards for warranted assertibility are the same as the
standards for knowledge, thus needs the premise that the standards for
warranted assertibility vary across contexts.
This DeRose contends is something to which every proponent of a WAO is
committed. But my high stakes WAM does
not require or presuppose that the standards for warranted assertibility change
as we move from low stakes to high stakes cases.
Any WAO is of course
committed to the context sensitivity of the warranted assertibility of
knowledge attributions—to the idea that a knowledge attribution may be
warrantedly asserted in one context but not in another. This, however, implies the contextual
variability of the standards for warranted assertibility of knowledge
attributions only if those standards are the sole relevant factor that can vary
with context. They are not. For the conversational implicatures
generated by knowledge attributions are relevant to their warranted
assertibility, and the implicatures generated by knowledge attributions can
vary across contexts. Asserting a
particular knowledge attribution can be warranted in one context but not in
another because it generates different implicatures in those contexts. If an assertion generates different
implicatures in different contexts, then an assertion can go from warranted to
unwarranted without a change in the standards for warranted assertibility.
This is what happens in the
WAO proposed above. Asserting that S
knows that P is warranted in L but not in H because different implicatures are
generated in those contexts. Asserting
that S knows that P in L generates the implicature that S is willing to stake X
on her epistemic relation to P; while asserting that S knows that P in H
generates the distinct implicature that S is willing to stake Y on that
same epistemic relation to P. By an
invariant standard of warranted assertibility—one to the effect that an
assertion is warranted only if it does not generate a false implicature—the
same assertion is warranted in L but not in H.
Asserting that S knows that P is unwarranted in H but not in L because
it generates a false implicature in H but not in L; it is not because the
standards for warranted assertibility have risen from L to H. The high stakes WAM is thus not committed in
any way to varying epistemic standards.
The chief bugaboo for
DeRose’s defense of epistemic contextualism in “Assertion, Knowledge, and
Context” is the concern that he is mistaking the contextual sensitivity of
warranted assertibility with the contextual variability of the standards for
warranted assertion.
4. The effectiveness of the high stakes WAM
In reference to a kind of WAM that he deems to be
effective, DeRose says:
Putting all of our criteria
together, we can see how much [the effective WAM] has going for it. It starts out with the advantage of being
aimed at an intuition that is a good candidate for being WAMed: an intuition
that an assertion would be false that is opposed by an intuition that the
opposite assertion would also be false in the relevant circumstances. It then explains away the relevant apparent
falsehood by appeal to the fact that a false implicature would be generated by
the assertion in the relevant situations—which, as we have seen, is less
problematic than is tryin to explain away the appearance of truth by appeal to
the generation of a true implicature.
And finally, it explains how the false implicature in question gets
generated by appeal to very general rules, rather than to ad hoc rules that
attaché only to sentences of the type in question. (193)
So according to DeRose, the following are jointly
sufficient for an effective WAM: (1) it is aimed at an intuition that some
assertion is false that is opposed by an intuition that the opposite assertion
would also be false; (2) it explains away an appearance of falsity by appeal to
a false implicature without attempting to implausibly explain away an
appearance of truth by appeal to a true implicature; and (3) it explains how
the relevant false implicature is generated by appeal to very general
conversational rules. I will now show
that by these criteria my high stakes WAM is effective.
Concerning (1): The high
stakes WAM tries to explain away the strong intuition that ‘S knows that P’ is
false in a high stakes situation H. But
there are equally strong intuitions that combine to support the claim that ‘S
does not know that P’ is also false in H.
First is the intuition that S does know that P in L on the basis of the
very same epistemic relation to P that she has in H; and second is the
intuition that the standards governing when an epistemic relation is adequate
are invariant across contexts. The
contextualist cannot deny the strength of the first intuition without denying
the support for her view; and she cannot deny the strength of the second
intuition without denying the significance of her view.
Concerning (2): The high stakes WAM does explain away the
intuition that ‘S knows that P’ is false in H by appeal to the fact that
asserting it generates a false implicature.
In H, asserting ‘S knows that P’ generates the implicature that S is
willing to stake some relatively high cost Y on her epistemic relation to P,
and S is not so willing. Now the high
stakes WAM does need to explain away the intuition that ‘S does not know that
P’ is true in H; but it can, and indeed must, do so without appealing to the
fact that the assertion generates a true implicature. It can do so as follows: ‘S does not know that P’ seems
true in H simply because its negation ‘S does know that P’ seems false in
H. It must do so, as we will see
in the next section, because asserting that S does not know that P does not
actually generate the implicature, which would be true, that S is not willing
to stake Y on her epistemic relation to P.
Concerning (3): Asserting ‘S
knows that P’ generates the implicature that S is willing to stake Y on her
epistemic relation to P in virtue of the general conversational rule that one
should assert only what one is willing to act on. When S asserts that P she is publicly endorsing P, and this
public endorsement has the effect (and is often intentionally made precisely to
have the effect) of inducing or inclining others to act on the truth of P. Since S should induce or incline others to
act on P only if she herself is willing to act on P, it follows that S should
assert P only if she is willing to act on P herself. We can call this the act account of assertion (AAA).
Now, when S* asserts in a
context C that S knows that P, S* is semantically implying that S would (under
suitable conditions) assert that P in C.
For to say that S knows that P is to say in part that S (strongly)
believes that P, which in turn is to say in part that S would assert that
P. So when S* claims that S knows that
P, she thereby implies that S would assert that P. That implication, given AAA, generates the implicature that S
would be willing to act on P. In a high
stakes context H, being willing to act on P means being willing to risk Y. So asserting that S knows that P in H
generates the implicature that S is willing to stake Y on her epistemic
relation to P; and it does so in virtue of AAA, which is a very general
conversational rule that does not attach only to knowledge attributions.[7]
So, putting all of DeRose’s
criteria together, we can see how much the high stakes WAM has going for
it. It is aimed at an intuition that is
a good candidate for being WAMed. It
explains away the relevant apparent falsehood by appeal to the fact that a
false implicature would be generated by the assertion in the relevant
situations. And finally, it explains
how the false implicature in question gets generated by appeal to very general
rules.
DeRose at one point
complains that:
No defender of invariantism
has proposed an account on which general rules of conversation together with
their proposed invariantist account of the truth-conditions of knowledge
attributions predict the pattern of varying conditions of warranted
assertibility of knowledge attributions that we encounter in natural
language. (176)
Well, the high stakes WAM combines a broadly Moorean
invariantist account of the truth-conditions of knowledge attributions with the
general rule of conversation that one should assert only what one is willing to
act on. And this combination does
predict the pattern of varying conditions of warranted assertibility that we
encounter in cases that involve raising what is practically at stake on the
truth of a certain proposition.
5. AAA and
Knowledge Denials
Given AAA, knowledge attributions of the form ‘S
knows that P’ generate conversational implicatures to the effect that S is willing
to act on P. Such attributions
semantically imply that S believes that P and thereby that S would assert that
P; and saying that S would assert that P implicates that S is willing to act on
P. Knowledge denials, however, of the
form ‘S does not know that P’ do not generate implicatures to the effect that S
is not willing to act on P. This turns
out to have a couple of significant consequences.
Before
we look at those consequences, let’s see exactly why knowledge denials do not
generate implicatures via AAA. To start
with, given that there are other necessary conditions for knowledge besides
belief, ‘S does not know that P’ does not by itself semantically imply that S
does not believe P or that S would not assert P. But if we accept KAA, of course, then saying that ‘S does not
know that P’ does pragmatically implicate that S would not assert that P. Still, this later claim does not then
implicate that S is not willing to act on P.
At least it does not do so via AAA.
For the act account of assertion claims that one should assert only
what one is willing to act on, not everything that one is willing to act
on. So the fact that S would not assert
that P does not implicate anything about S’s willingness to act on P. S might turn out to be some kind of
epistemic daredevil, willing to act on all kinds of things she does not know,
without violating any conversational rules.
Now
let’s take a look at the consequences of the fact that AAA does not help
generate any implicatures from knowledge denials. First, this fact explains why we must account for the apparent
truth of ‘S does not know that P’ in a high stakes context H by appeal to the
fact that ‘S knows that P’ merely seems false because its assertion is unwarranted. We cannot say, even if we wanted to, that ‘S
does not know that P’ merely seems true in H because it generates a true
implicature and is therefore a warranted assertion. Though it is true in H that S is not willing to risk Y on her
epistemic relation to P, asserting ‘S does not know that P’ does not generate
that claim as an implicature.
Second,
the fact that AAA does not help generate any implicatures from knowledge
denials shows why we must make a Moorean WAO and employ a high stakes WAM in
response to contextualist cases. We
cannot, on the basis of AAA, make a Cartesian WAO and employ a low stakes
WAM. For, we cannot effectively explain
away our intuition that ‘S knows that P’ is true in some low stakes context L
by saying that it merely seems true because it generates a true implicature and
is therefore a warranted assertion.
That attribution does generate what would be a true implicature that S
is willing to act on P in L. But as
DeRose has pointed out, the general strategy of explaining away the appearance
of truth by relying on a true implicature is problematic.[8] This leaves us with having to account for
the merely apparent truth of ‘S knows that P’ in L on the basis of the merely
apparent falsity in L of ‘S does not know that P.’ But we cannot account for
the apparent falsity of that denial by claiming that it generates a false
implicature and is therefore unwarranted.
Though it is false in L that S is not willing to risk X on her epistemic
relation to P, asserting ‘S does not know that P’ does not generate that clam
as an implicature.
The act account of assertion
thus provides the resources for an effective Moorean WAO to the contextualists’
most compelling cases but not for an effective Cartesian WAO to those
cases. Thus it seems at this point that
if we want to be invariantists, we ought to prefer a common sense epistemology
with relatively low epistemic standards to a more philosophical epistemology
with relatively high epistemic standards.
6.
Conclusion
DeRose concludes “Assertion, Knowledge, and Context”
by saying
Not only does [the warranted
assertibility objection] fail the tests we have discerned, but, as we saw
above…what a close look at the conditions for warranted assertibility actually
leads to is a powerful argument in favor of contextualism” (194).
I have presented here, however, a particular WAO
that passes those tests and avoids the argument from the knowledge account of
assertion. The high stakes WAM explains
away the intuition that ‘S knows that P’ is false in a high stakes context by
showing how that assertion generates a false implicature in virtue of the
general conversational rule that one should assert only what one is willing to
act on. Moreover, the high stakes WAM
accounts for the context sensitivity of warranted assertibility for knowledge attributions
without presupposing a contextual variability in the standards of warranted
assertibility for knowledge attributions.
Since the argument from KAA to contextualism presupposes a contextual
variation in the standards of warranted assertibility for knowledge
attributions, that argument does not undermine the high stakes WAM.
The
high stakes WAM poses a general challenge for the contextualist. She needs to produce a pair of cases where S knows that P in one but not
the other because the standards for knowledge have gone up. The most compelling pairs of cases involve
raising what is practically at stake on the truth of P to the point where S is
unwilling to act on her given epistemic relation to P. Any such case however is susceptible to the
high stakes WAM. A Moorean invariantist
can say that S really does know that P in the relevant high stakes case, though
it appears that she does not because saying so generates the false implicature
that S is willing to risk some relatively high stake on her epistemic relation
to P. Given that the high stakes WAM is
effective and avoids the argument from the knowledge account of assertion, the
contextualist is left with the task of finding an intuitively compelling pair
of cases to support her view that do not crucially rely on raising what is
practically at stake for some agent on the truth of a proposition.
[1] All parenthetical page references are to: DeRose, Keith. “Assertion, Knowledge, and Context”, The Philosophical Review, Vol. III, No. 2. (April 2002).
[2] I intend the notion of an epistemic relation to P to be neutral on the question of internalism vs. externalism.
[3] The Bank Cases originally appear in DeRose, “Contextualism and Knowledge Attributions”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (1992).
[4] The knowledge account of assertion has been defended by G.E. Moore in his Commonplace Book: 1919-1953 (London: Allen & Unwin, 1962); by Peter Unger in his Ignorance (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1975); and by Timothy Williamson in his Knowledge and its Limits (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000). The knowledge account of assertion can take the form of a claim that when one asserts a proposition one thereby represents oneself as knowing that P (as Moore would have it); or it can take the form of a constitutive rule of the practice of asserting that one should assert only what one knows (as Williamson would have it). DeRose takes these two different forms to be ‘two sides of the same coin’.
[5] See, Moore, op. cit., p. 277
[6] DeRose says, “it makes the relevant [contextualist supporting] intuitions more stable if …the raise in epistemic standards is tied to a very practical concern” (169). And in “The Ordinary Language Basis of Contextualism”, forthcoming Philosophical Quarterly, he says that the best case pairs for “deciding between contextualism and invariantism in the first place…will be a low standards case where the stakes are low…and a high standards case where the stakes are high.”
[7] In using the ambiguous formulation ‘asserting that S knows that P in H’, I am avoiding certain complications concerning whether the assertion is made in the same context that it is talking about.
[8] He says, “By contrast, it seems much more problematic to claim that an assertion that seems true is in fact false by means of a claim that, though the assertion itself is false, it generates a true implicature and is therefore a warranted assertion. For, except where we engage in special practices of misdirection, like irony or hyperbole, don’t we want to avoid falsehood both in what we implicate and (especially) in what we actually say? So, it would seem that a false assertion will remain unwarranted despite whatever true implicatures it might generate.” (193)