Ethics, Part II: The mind

The topic of Part II is the human mind, the knowledge of which, together with that of God, is necessary to attain blessedness.  The argument of this part can be divided into 4 main sections.
1) definitions and axioms
2) The nature of the mind and its relation to the body (Prop 1-15)
3) the intellect and the extent of human knowledge (16-47)
4) the will, its alleged freedom and its relation to the intellect. (48-9)
Here we do only 1,2 and 4.

A. Definitions and axioms

Def. 1: the point here is that a body is a mode of God as extended.
Def. 2: the point is that the essence of a thing X is the necessary and sufficient condition of X.
At IIp10note, S explains why he does not say that the essence of a thing is that without which the thing cannot be or be conceived (otherwise God would belong to the essence of everything)
Def. 3: "By idea, I mean the mental conception which is formed by the mind as a thinking thing"
As S explains, he emphasizes the activity of the mind in conceiving objects.  It turns out that for S. to have an idea is to conceive of something, or to have a belief about it, not merely to have a mental picture or mental description of it. (see IIp49)
Def. 4: an adequate idea is one which has all the intrinsic properties of a true idea.  The extrinsic properties of a true idea is the agreement with its ideatum. S doesn't explain what the intrinsic properties are. Probably what he has in mind is that an idea is adequate if it is possible to deduce from it the ideas of the properties of the ideatum. Example: the idea of triangle.
For S, all adequate ideas are true and vice versa.
Def. 5: Duration is the indefinite continuation of a thing.  That is, attributing duration to something says nothing about how long it exists.
Def. 6: by reality and perfection I mean the same thing.
Def. 7: the point is that an individual thing is a finite thing with determinate existence.

Axioms

Ax. 1: the essence of man doesn't involve existence: any man could not exist.
Ax. 2: man thinks
Ax. 3: The point here is that the modes of thinking, e.g., love, desire (the emotions), presuppose the idea of the object of the emotion but not vice versa.
Ax. 4: We feel a certain body to be affected in many ways.
Ax. 5: We do not feel or perceive any individual thing except bodies and modes of thinking.
 

B. The nature of the mind and its relation to the body (1-15).

Props. 1 &2: Thought and extension are attributes of God, since God has all the attributes.
Prop. 3: "In God there is necessarily the idea not only of his essence, but also of all things which necessarily follow from his essence.
The idea behind the proof is that since thought is an infinite attribute of God expressing God's essence, in God there must be the    idea of what flows from that essence.
In sum, in God there is an idea for every thing.
Prop. 4: The idea of God is one since God is one.
Props 5-6: The point here is that each attribute is a closed causal system, since each attribute is conceived through itself, and consequently nothing in it can be caused by what is outside the attribute.
NOTE: This is an implicit attack on Descartes' interactionism.
In the note, S. attacks the view that extended things are created because God has ideas of them.
Prop. 7: "The order and connection of ideas is the same as the order and connection of things.
Proof: This proposition is evident from Iax4. For the idea of everything that is caused depends on a knowledge of the cause, whereof it is an effect."

Prop. 8: This is rather obscure, but it seems to amount to the claim that IIp7 extends not only to actually existing things, but to possibilities as well.
Prop. 9: this holds that since every finite thing depends on God viewed from the point of view of finite modes, so every idea of a finite thing depends on God viewed from the perspective of finite modes in the attribute of thought.
Prop. 10: man is not a substance; its essence is to be a definite mode of the divine attributes.
Prop. 11: "the first element which constitutes the actual being of the human mind is the idea of some particular actually existing thing." Prop. 12: It follows from IIp7 that everything which happens in the body must be perceived by the human mind.
Problem: this seems quite hard to accept; certainly it should not entail that we are aware of all that happens in our bodies. S. needs a theory of the unconscious, or at least a theory of confusion. He has neither.
Prop. 13: The object of the mind is the body.

C. The will, its alleged freedom and its relation to the understanding (props. 48-9)

The last two propositions of part II are devoted to a brief study of the will. S. concentrates on Descartes' theory of the will in Meditation IV and in the Principles: will as free and the cause of assent to propositions.
Prop. 48: there is no free, i.e., self-caused (self-initiating) will because the mind is a finite mode of God.
NOTE: In the note, S. claims that the same point can be made for any other mental operation, e.g., understanding, loving, desiring etc.  He takes this to show that there is no Faculty of will, understanding etc., but mere individual acts of volition, understanding etc.  Faculties are a product of the imagination, like Aristotelian natural kinds.
Prop. 49: "there is in the mind no volition, that is, affirmation or negation, except that which an idea, insofar as it is an idea, involves."

D. Conclusion
If  S.'s enterprise is successful, the consequences are revolutionary:


Spinoza's political philosophy.

S's views are contained in two works, the Theological-Political Treatise (TPT) and the Political Treatise (PT) left unfinished at his death.  Both show Hobbes's influence.  Here we look mostly at two chapters of the former work, occasionally making use of material from the latter.  By and large, the political views espoused in these two works are the same, with one important exception involving the constitution of the commonwealth.

1.
God or nature, whose essence is power, is absolutely free.  Hence it has a right to all things; that is, God's right is coextensive with God's power.  But since there's no ontological inertia, individual modes (e.g., humans) exist only insofar as they embody divine power.  Hence, their right is also coextensive with their power.  In other words, might makes right (PT II, 3).  Hence:

2.
Hence, in the state of nature nobody is safe and nobody can cultivate the mind or live well; in short, humans live in what Hobbes would consider a state of war.  As a result, one's actual power, i.e., one's actual right, is in effect very limited.  So, humans attempt to exit the state of nature and form a commonwealth.
At these point, S gives two accounts:
  1. the TPT account: everyone resolves and contracts 1) to behave according to reason and bridle one's appetites.  However, in order to insure that such a compact is kept, everyone also agrees 2) to transfer one's rights to society as a whole in order to enforce the compact.  The result is a democracy.

  2. NOTES:
  3. The PT account: moved by their passions (e.g., fear and hope), men join forces, without a deliberate and rational design to improve their lives.  Moreover, no contract is mentioned (although S does allow that a people may transfer its right to a sovereign (TP IV,6)).

  4. NOTE:
    This account sits better with S's view in TP that men in the state of nature are barely rational (TP II, 15)
3.
The sovereign, as for Hobbes, is absolute: decides what's right or wrong (and therefore cannot wrong the subjects), and determines the doctrine and practices of religion (TTP XIX).
NOTE: The point here is similar to Hobbes's: without these rights, the sovereign would be unable to govern.
However, having equated right with power, S holds that the sovereign's right extends only as far as his power.  Hence, the transfer of rights is never total because the sovereign does not have the power, and hence the right, In fact, S goes even further and claims that the sovereign doesn't have the absolute right to do what diminishes his power.  Hence, the sovereign has no right to pass laws which are so hated or have such consequences that his power will be diminished.  In particular, S argues, every citizen should think what he likes and say what he thinks.
Rationale: However: NOTE:
hence, S's liberal views are rather moderate; in particular, he's ready to hold a rigid separation between thought and action, so that the enlightened man will try to reason with a stupid sovereign but, if he fails to change the law, will obey without any form of disobedience.