A) DUALISM
i. Substance Dualism. The mind and the body are different types of substance irreducible one to the other. Substance dualists often disagree on the nature of the soul (the substance of the mind). For example, Descartes thought that the soul is unextended and not in space; Clarke, by contrast, thought it extended and in space.
First Argument for substance dualism
Second Argument for Substance Dualism
Problems for Substance Dualism
How do our souls causally interact with our bodies? Why is my
mind so radically affected by what goes on in my body?
ii. Property Dualism.
This theory makes two main claims
B) MATERIALISM.
There are two main varieties of materialism with respect to the mind/body
problem, Identity Theory, and Eliminativism
i. Identity theory.
ii. Eliminativism.
Mental states do not exists much in the same way in which supernatural
powers or ghosts don't exist. In particular, the explanatory power of folk
psychology is minimal: it tells nothing about why we sleep, of how memory
works, of hemineglect, alexia without agraphia (write well, but unable
to read), etc.. It is so wrong that it will eventually be completely
abandoned, much in the same way in which the caloric or flogiston theories
have been abandoned without being reduced to statistical mechanics or chemistry.
C) THEORIES neutral between dualism and monism, but with materialist leanings.
i. Behaviorism
In 1950, Alan Turing proposed that if one carries on remote conversations with a computer and another human, and cannot determine which is which, then tthe computer counts as intelligent. This has come to be known as the Turing Test for computer intelligence. Although the Turing Test can be undrestood in different ways (as providing good evidence for intelligence, or as providing a certain criterion for intelligence), if one believes that the capacity to pass the test is what it is to be intelligent, then one is a behaviorist about intelligence. That is, a behaviorist about intelligence believes that all there is to being intelligent is being disposed to respond appropriately to certain kinds of stimulations, in this case, the questions involved in the remote converstions. More broadly, a behaviorist about some mental state says that all there is to being in that state is being disposed to behave in specific ways in response to specific sorts of stimulation.
Problems for behaviorism
ii. Functionalism
Suppose we want to explain what the different parts of a car are, and
that we have a theory of how the different parts of a car interact with
each other,
and with things our audience already understands, like air and gasoline.
The theory might look something like this:
Car Theory: ...and the carburetor mixes gasoline and air and sends the mixture to the ignition chamber, which in turn.....and that makes the wheels turn.
We can now define what it is to be a carburetor and an ignition
chamber as follows:
A carburetor = that thing x which mixes gasoline and air and sends the mixture to another thing y, which in turn...and that makes the wheels turn.An ignition chamber = that thing z such that there's another thing w , and w mixes gasoline and air and sends the mixture to z, which in turn...and that makes the wheels turn.
In other words, we explain what a carburetor is in terms of how
it interacts with ignition chambers and with other things. Notice that
we've explained what a carburetor and an ignition chamber are in terms
of the causal roles they play, as specified in our Car Theory. So,
any pair of things which play the appropriate causal roles count as a carburetor
and an ignition chamber. The details of their physical construction are
not important. To be a carburetor, it doesn't matter what you're made out
of; only that you do the right job. (The same goes for ignition chambers.)
The basic idea of functionalism is to do the same with respect to the
mind. Suppose we have a theory about how our various mental states
are causally related to each other, and to input and output:
Mental Theory: ...and pain is caused by pin pricks, and pain causes worry and the emission of loud noises, and worry in turn causes brow-wrinkling...
Assuming that our audience already understands things such as various
sorts of sensory stimulation, and behavioral output, we can now define
what it is to be in pain, and to be worried, as follows:
A person is in pain = there's x such that there's a y, ... and x is caused by pin pricks, and x causes y and the emission of loud noises, and y in turn causes brow-wrinkling..., and the person has x.A person is worried = there's a z such that there's a w, ...and w is caused by pin pricks, and w causes z and the emission of loud noises, and z in turn causes brow-wrinkling... , and the person has z.
The functionalist thinks that all of our mental states can be defined
in this way. Anything which has states playing those causal roles
counts as having a
mind. Whenever such thing is in the first of those states, it's in
pain, and when it's in the second of those states, it's worried. It does
not matter what the intrinsic make-up of those states is. In humans, they
are certain kinds of brain states. In Martians, they would likely be different
sorts of states. In an appropriately programmed computer, they would be
electronic states. These would be different physical realizations of the
same causal roles. The functionalist identifies our mental states with
the causal roles they play. How those roles are realized is not important.
In this respect, the science of the mind is methodologically autonomous
from physical sciences, just as software is autonomous from hardware.
The functionalist thinks that minds and mental processes are exactly
analogous to software and to the changes that a piece of software undergoes
as it's running. So long as there's some hardware with some internal states
that stand in the right causal relations to each other and to input and
output, you've got a mind. A line of reasoning often offered in support
this view is the following. At some level of description, the brain
is a device that receives complex inputs from the sensory organs and sends
complex outputs to the motor system. The brain's activity is well-behaved
enough to be specifiable in terms of various (incredibly complicated) causal
relationships, just like a very complex computer program.
Broadly speaking, there are two main varieties of functionalism, depending on the sort of mental theory one uses to define the functional roles:
1. The Inverted Spectrum
Many experiences have two different kinds of features: representational
features (For instance, your visual experience may represent that there
is something red in front of you), and qualitative features (There is "something
it is like" to have them). So, if you suffer from Daltonism, my seeing
a green square and your seeing the same green square have the same (or
similar) representational features, but different qualitative features
(you see a shade of grey while I see green). By qualia one
means the qualitative features of experiences, what's like to have them.
Suppose now that objects we both call green look to me the way objects
we both call red look to you. Suppose also that mentally we are functionally
equivalent. Still, there's a big difference which functionalism cannot
capture: my quale of what we call 'green' is red; yours is green.
So, functionalism cannot give a full account of the mind: it leaves out
qualia.
Replies:
ii. Searle's Chinese Room (see essay)