Religion
and Morality
Morality has a long association with religion, and on most ethics panel
there's a minister. So, it’s natural to ask whether morality essentially
depends on religion.
Some philosophers (e.g., Anscombe) have argued as follows:
- Contemporary morality uses the notion of moral
obligation.
- The notion of moral obligation presupposes that of
moral law.
- But a legalistic system of morality presupposes a
law-giver.
- However, laws and norms of human society and individual
conscience won't do because they are often wrong, absurd and
idiosyncratic, as history amply shows.
- Hence, the only plausible law-giver left is God.
- So, contemporary morality entails a divine law theory
of obligation in which moral laws are divine commands.
If the previous argument is correct, atheism precludes the possibility of
morality; in other words, a secular morality is impossible, a conclusion sometimes
drawn by theists
1. The basic meta-ethical issue of Divine Command Theory deals with
- the relation between God's commands and morality.
- the role of God in moral knowledge
- the role of God in moral motivation.
i. The
relation between God's commands and morality:
- Right actions are right just because God
approves of them and wrong actions are wrong just because God disapproves
of them (theological voluntarism). Then, God is a legislator of morality;
he decides what's right or wrong in the same way in which the state
decides what's legal and what's illegal.
Problems:
- divine commands run the
risk of being arbitrary.
NOTE: one cannot say that murder is forbidden by God because it’s wrong,
if being wrong amounts to being forbidden by God. That is, on what
basis does God decide what's wrong? Obviously, not on a moral
basis.
- When religious people
say that God is moral, they want to convey more than a simple
truism. But this is possible only if God follows the moral law,
which, therefore, cannot depend on his will or promulgation.
- If God commanded to
kill the innocent, would murder still be wrong? On mount Moriah,
was Abraham a murderous (i.e., a morally wrong) religious fanatic?
Many would answer “yes” to both questions. The reason is that many think that the
moral qualities of an action are supervenient on its non-moral ones, that
is, they depend on objective features of the action itself, not on
whether god happens to like it or not.
In fact, one might hold that moral truths, like the laws of
arithmetic, are necessary, and therefore not subject to divine power.
- Theological voluntarism
looks suspiciously like subjectivism on a grand scale.
- Divine commands may be
morally binding only if they are recognized as such. But the existence of more than half a
billion atheists indicates that god has failed to publicize
properly. Since such failure on
god’s side is impossible, morality must be independent of divine
commands.
- God approves of right actions because they are right
and disapproves of wrong actions because they are wrong (theological objectivism).
Then, God is a mere transmitter of values (and not a very good one at
that), much in the same way in which a math teacher is a transmitter of
math which, however, do not depend on her.
Problem: Is theological objectivism sufficient to base a religious
morality? If God is a mere transmitter, what's essentially religious
about morality?
Note
that this does not exclude the fact that we may have special duties toward god
because he’s our maker, he’s perfect, he owns our abode, and so on, and that
consequently He may have moral grounds for asking us to behave thus and so
because of our relation to him. Of
course, this also entails that God had moral duties toward us.
ii. The
role of God in moral knowledge
One might hold that morality is religious in the weak sense that God is the only transmitter of morality.
On this view the dependence of morality on religion is epistemological.
True, there are atheists who seem to know that murder is wrong, but they
don't fully know it; they are like non-physicists talking about atoms:
they may get it right, but they are unable to justify or warrant their
beliefs.
Problem: This view is hard to support. That certain actions are
known to be morally wrong seems the starting point of morality. Presumably, one’s ground for one’s belief
that murder is wrong is not worse than the one a religious person could offer
or for the claim that god exists.
iii. The role of God in moral motivation.
One might argue that the presence of a God who will punish and reward us in the
afterlife on the basis of our deeds is a necessary component of moral
motivation. The issue is complicated because the question “why be moral?” is
difficult to answer.
The question is, of course, a challenge to justify one’s
adherence to morality. One must show that well informed rational beings would
choose to behave morally. One can think of two types of
justification:
1. internal
(validation). This is within ethics
itself: we have a good moral reason to be moral, and that's all that
is required
2. external
(vindication). Here one is asking:
why should the moral way of life have priority over other conflicting ways of
life (religious, self interested etc.)? An external justification
addresses a global issue: why should I be moral at all? Brief
reflection shows that this can be an impossible question to answer if it
requires to show that morality should have priority even from the standpoint of
another, and opposed, way of life. For example, if self-interest
and morality do come into conflict, it would be unreasonable to demand that the
defender of morality show that from the standpoint of self-interest we
should be moral. Or, if religion and morality conflict (think of Abraham
on mount Moriah), it would be absurd to require a religious
justification for why one ought to choose morality rather than religion. Of course, one might believe, like Clarke,
that morality and religion never conflict, and that when they seem to disagree
one only has to look more carefully to find agreement, but that may be wishful
thinking.
Since typically morality is thought to conflict with self-interest, here’s
an argument stating the problem:
I.
One has a reason to behave morally only if doing
so is in one’s self-interest
II.
At times behaving morally conflicts with
self-interest
III.
Hence, at times one has no reason to behave
morally
Criticism of (I):
·
It embodies a request for vindication. But some philosophers, e.g., Kant, have
rejected this as misguided, claiming that the answer to “Why should I be
moral?” is “Because it is moral.”
Asking for another justification betrays a misunderstanding of the very
nature of morality. Morality is not
prudence.
·
It’s not clear why only self-interest would
provide a reason for action. Why should
other-regardedness be irrational? What
are the criteria of rationality here?
·
Maybe the evolutionary foundation for prosocial
behavior and (probably) for morality provides a warranty for morality
Criticism of (II):
·
Morality is its own reward. For example, self-sacrifice ennobles one
(Aristotle), or immorality deforms one’s character (Plato), etc. Doing wrong may provide some advantage but
thwarts our nature preventing us from achieving true happiness (vs. mere
contentment).
·
Behaving morally is always advantageous. Here things are easier for theists. For example, Paley thought that since God
exists, wants us to be moral, and will punish and reward accordingly in the
next (eternal!) life without fail, real self-interest and morality never
diverge. Or, one might argue, as Hume did, that behaving immorally while
pretending to be moral (the obvious case in which immorality seems
advantageous) is psychologically too demanding and ultimately leads to
unhappiness. Or that giving in to
temptation even once makes it easier to give in again, which increases the
chance of getting caught and punished.
However:
- At a minimum one might argue that acting out of fear
has little or no moral worth. As Kant puts it, threats extort but
fail to impose moral obligation.
- Knowledge that
divine justice will be brought about makes some forms of
self-sacrifice, e.g., laying down one’s life believing that there’s no
afterlife, or going though hardship believing that no recompense will
follow, impossible
- As a matter of fact, many atheists behave morally
without any fear of punishment in the afterlife.
2. Problems with sacred texts
and their teachings
- Which texts or oral traditions constitute God's message
to us? The Hebrew Bible? The Christian Bible? If so, which
version? The Koran? The Book of Mormon? Some
other text in some other culture?
- How does one decipher God's will from the
Scriptures? This presents two types of problem:
- The Bible is a very old
text, the compositional details of which are very often obscure and whose
interpretation is often controversial. Compare this with the US
constitution, written in relatively clear English about 200 years ago by
people who have left letters and documents on the details of its
composition and the politics of its adoption. And yet its interpretation
is far from obvious, as the nasty political battles for each new supreme court
justice and the split decisions of the court indicate. That scriptural
interpretation could reasonably be any easier defies belief; in fact, one
should expect it to be much harder.
- Scriptural divine
behavior, what God does, commands, and allows, is at times immoral and
occasionally grossly so, involving, for example, wholesale slaughter of
children and pregnant women (Hosea 13:16), slavery (Lev, 25:44-46) the
beating of slaves to death as long as they survive for two days (Ex.
20:20-21), stoning (Lev 24:16; Numbers 15 32-36), and genocide (Josh.
1-12), not to mention the various prophecies in Revelation. Hence, one is left with either a grossly immoral
god, or with the need to explain away the relevant texts. Since we are
dealing with morality, the former is not really an option. But then we
are left with the task of interpreting religion in the light of
morality. That is, we use morality to determine the boundaries of
what "proper" religion should say, an enterprise that seems
reasonable only if we ourselves are already prepared to
assess moral standards, at least partially independently of
religion.
- Since sacred texts are very often opaque, it's very
tempting, and historically very frequent, to read them so as to have God
say whatever we want God to say, which is not only blasphemous but
all too often also has given, and perhaps still gives, religious sanction
to sexism, racism, intolerance, and other immoral dispositions adopted,
perhaps in good faith, by those who have religious authority at the time.
- Since Scriptures are obviously errant in factual
matters and some of its teachings are grossly immoral, it’s reasonable to
conclude that they were not divinely inspired but rather written by men
who today would be considered racist, sexist, and genocidal ignoramuses. So, what reason do we have to accept
what they say as binding just
because they say it?
3. So, bracketing religious considerations far from threatening
ethics is often a precondition for doing ethics reasonably.