Non-consequentialist
theories
Non-consequentialist theories claim that what we ought to do does not depend
on the consequences of our actions. There are different and
conflicting types of non-consequentialist theories. Here we look at
Kant’s theory.
Kant’s Deontology
One way to approach Kant’s theory is to contrast it with
Utilitarianism. For the latter, the right depends on something else, the
good: what's right is to maximize the good; the right is a means to bring about
the good.
By contrast, for Kant the right does not depend on anything else: morality is,
in this respect, autonomous.
For K., morality has three formal features:
1. It applies to persons, i.e. all beings endowed with a rational will, i.e., all beings capable of making decisions on the basis of rules of behavior. In K’s jargon, morality is universal
2. It applies to persons always and in all cases. In K’s jargon, morality is necessary.
3. Moral obligation presupposes
the power to carry it out: One is morally obliged to do X only if it is in
one's power to do X. In other words, for
K. “I ought to” implies “I can.”
(1)-(3) together
lead to two important conclusions:
i.
As
a person is under moral obligation at all times and in all situations, a person
must have the power to do what is right at all times and in all
situations. But the only thing that is
always in a person’s power is her will, her intentions. So, the
morality of an action must depend on the intention of the agent and not on
consequences or emotions, or feelings because none of these is wholly within
the agent’s power.
NOTE: For K., this consideration suffices to rule out
Consequentialism.
ii.
Because
of (1), the ground of the moral law cannot rest on any consideration of what's
empirically true of man or any other specific person, but on a-priori (i.e., non-empirical)
considerations about what it is to be a person, that is, to have a rational
will.
Thought Question: Can
Consequentialism address K’s charges by using the distinction between the
morality of the action and that of the agent?
1) A good will, the decision to follow the moral law because it is
right, is the only thing that is good without qualification, independently of
its success. While other capacities, e.g., intelligence, gifts of fortune,
talent, can operate against morality (think of a clever thief), a good
will always acts in accordance with the principles of morality.
NOTE:
K. is very insistent on the motive of duty because:
·
Even praiseworthy emotions and feelings need not
lead to the moral decision in all cases
·
Morality requires acting with the goal of being
right
Of course, often our actions stem from mixed motives
involving duty and emotions/feelings.
2) The moral worth of a
decision lies in the maxim (the principle or rule) according to which it has
been made, that is, the maxim on the basis of which the will
has operated.
So, the shopkeeper acted from the maxim “Don’t cheat your customers if you want
good business” or, alternatively, from the maxim “Don’t steal.”
3) A specific maxim is moral if
it stems from the Categorical Imperative,
an abstract maxim any fully rational person would follow.
Kant
gives different formulations of the Categorical Imperative which he claims
are equivalent (whether they are is a matter of debate). Two
are especially important:
NOTE:
Although strictly speaking there is only one Categorical Imperative, one
can call any maxim which satisfies (1) and/or (2) a
categorical imperative. For
example, we shall see that ‘Don’t steal’ satisfies (1)-(2) and therefore we may
call it a, but not the, categorical imperative
4) A categorical imperative must be distinguished from a hypothetical
imperative:
·
A
categorical imperative is a command whose justification does not presuppose any
further end but consists in the fact that it satisfies both the universal and
the end in itself formulas.
·
A
hypothetical imperative is a command whose justification depends on what one
wants. For example, ‘If you want good business, don't cheat
your customers’ is a hypothetical imperative because the justification
for the command ‘Don't cheat your customers’ depends on the desirability
of having good business.
NOTE: Hence, a hypothetical imperative carries no implication that one
ought to do what it commands (I might give up the idea of having good
business). By contrast, a categorical imperative implies that one
ought to do what it states because, K believes, its justification rests on
something that any rational person would approve of.
5) The universal law
version of CI says ‘Act only on the maxim through which you can at the
same time will that it be a universal law.’
Rationale: it determines maxims which
could be adopted by persons without
assuming anything specific about their desires, capacities or social relations,
which are merely contingent, dependent on fortune; in other words it determines
maxims that would be adopted by a rational person as such. Keep in mind that the moral law applies to
all, and therefore cannot depend on whether you are rich, poor, intelligent,
powerful, etc.
6) Application
of the Universal Law formula
CI provides us with a test to determine what to will, that
is, whether an action is moral, immoral or merely permissible. However,
how this is supposed to work is far from clear, and Kant’s own examples
don't help too much. A possible
reconstruction is as follows.
A.
Test for perfect duties.
·
has
a corresponding right. So, you have
right not to be lied to
·
can
be always satisfied: it’s possible for me not to lie to anyone.
Problem: Consider now M =
"always borrow money, but never lend it", and N = "never borrow
money, but always lend it." Both M
and N would be pragmatically self-defeating if everybody followed them
(borrowers need lenders and vice versa).
And yet one is hard pressed in understanding why either would be morally
wrong.
B. Test for imperfect duties.
Same as above with one difference: at (4) substitute "incompatible with
some basic features of rational will" for "pragmatically
self-defeating."
Example 1:
M is
incompatible with the successful pursuit of desirable goals, an outcome
no rational being would want. So, N is an imperfect duty.
Example 2:
M
fails the test because a rational being sets ends for himself the satisfaction
of which requires talent and skill, intellectual and otherwise.
NOTE: an imperfect duty is one which cannot be satisfied by all agents in all
actions towards all persons (e.g., we cannot help everybody). Imperfect duties are duties of beneficence and
·
have
no corresponding rights. So, I have a
duty to help you but you have no right to my help
·
typically
can be satisfied only selectively: I can’t help everybody.
7) The "end in itself" formulation of CI says: “Treat
humanity in your own person or in the person of any other never simply as
a means but always at the same time as an end.”
Rationale:
Since humans are persons (beings endowed with a rational will), they have
intrinsic objective value and hence they are ends in themselves.
Since the value of everything else is parasitic on that of persons and a
means is less valuable than its end, treating persons merely as means
amounts to denying that they are ends in themselves, that is, persons.
The meaning of the maxim is made clearer by the following:
Thought Question: how does one deal with cases of false
consciousness?
Rationale
of the end-in–itself rule:
A rational will manifests itself in the link between one's values and what one
does. Treating people as means weakens the link; treating them as
ends enhances it.
Thought
Question. Suppose
that Jane is convicted of stealing and the judge proceeds to sentence her. Now Jane protests that she doesn't want to be
sentenced saying: "If you sentence me you will simply be using me for your
(and society's) ends." Is she right from a Kantian perspective?
8) In following CI, a
rational being is autonomous, since
one follows the rational code of behavior which one, insofar as rational, has
oneself created. This is analogous to
following rational laws in one's reasoning.
9)
Virtue is a firm disposition to
fulfill one's duty (i.e. to follow CI out of duty). A mark of
virtue is a feeling of joy in performing one's duty. Note that such
feeling is not involved in the
motive of a moral action.
10) Kant’s view culminates in what he calls “the kingdom of
ends.” Consider a “systematic union” of all rational beings acting
on the basis of good will, i.e., on the basis of universal and morally
necessary laws. Then, since laws determine ends with regard to
their “universal validity, we shall be able--if we abstract from the
personal differences between rational beings, and also from the content of
their private ends-- to conceive...a kingdom of ends which is possible in
accordance with the above principles [i.e., CI].”
John Rawls has proposed that we take Kant to ask which maxims we would
want to be universal law not from the standpoint of our individual
situation (talents, race, sex, wealth, etc., including conceptions of
non-moral good), but from that of a rational person who doesn't know
his own individual situation (this is another way of saying that in
justifying universal maxims, we cannot appeal to our, or anybody's,
individual situation). Form behind this “veil of ignorance,” we all would
choose those maxims which guarantee that our dignity as persons be
satisfied and we be able to pursue our individual conceptions of
non-moral good, whatever they might be, thus combining the two versions
of CI we have considered.
11) Problems
Two features that some find appealing are that K’s ethics forbids certain action absolutely and often can provide certainty that one has done the right thing (Compare this with Consequentialism). However, this comes at a cost:
1. Rigorism.
Kant’s ethics is case-insensitive. For example, Kant claims that
one should never lie. But what should one do when someone's life is
at stake? Should the Danish fisherman smuggling Jews to
Sweden tell the truth to the Nazi officer on the patrol boat?
Most of us would say “no”, but Kant says “yes”. (Notice that being
silent won't do here). Kant might argue that telling the truth is a perfect
duty (the Nazi has a right not to be lied to) while helping others is an imperfect duty (the Jew hasn't a right
to be helped). But many would find this answer appalling. Of course
one should lie to the Nazi.
Replies:
·
Perhaps
Kant overstated the requirements of CI. “Lie when and only when it
is necessary to save the life of an innocent person” seems to pass the
universal law test because its range is small enough not to destroy the
institution of promise keeping, without which the maxim would become
self-defeating.
Even so, it's hard to see how the maxim would satisfy the end in itself
version of CI.
NOTE: this raises the further problem of the equivalence of the various versions
of CI.
·
Perhaps
one could do some fancy footwork with the notion of lying. For example, one might say that telling a lie
involves not only intentionally telling a falsehood but doing so to a person
who has the right to be told the truth.
Since one may argue that the Nazi has no right to know the truth. The
fisherman is not lying to him.
2. Insensitivity to the good
Kant’s ethics may require of
us that we make the world less of a good or happy place: if it’s my duty to do
X and doing so will result in the production of much unhappiness, I still have
to do X. Kant’s answer is that it’s not
the role of morality to produce happiness.
3.
Difficulty
in addressing conflicts between two perfect duties or two imperfect
duties. For example, I have a perfect duty
to tell the truth and also a perfect duty not to harm you. But what if telling the truth will harm you?
4.
For
K. only intentional actions have any moral standing. But many actions may be the result of
organizations or movements without any clear decisional structure, and yet we
would want to say that such actions are moral or immoral. (Note that Util. does not have this problem
at all).