Consequentialism
Consequentialism evaluates actions on the basis of how much good they produce. This raises two issues:
1. Good for whom?
2. What counts as good?
For (1), we could say that the only individual who counts is the agent (ethical egoism), or the agent plus the agent’s group, or all persons, or all sentient beings, including animals (utilitarianism).
For (2), we could say that there is only one good thing, happiness, and that everything else is good only as a means to happiness; or we could say that there are several goods such as happiness, knowledge, virtue, or pleasure.
Leaving (1) aside for the moment, with respect to (2) there are at least three reasonable options available:
1. Hedonistic consequentialism,
which identifies the good with pleasure and absence of pain (this is
utilitarianism).
2.
Subjectivist
consequentialism, which identifies the good with the satisfaction of individual
preference.
Problem: It collapses the desirable into the desired. But the two
at times don't coincide. For example:
o
People
often don't know what's good for them or are unable to choose it because of
lack of information, irrationality, false consciousness, or weakness of the
will.
o One might argue that some
things, e.g., love, beauty, friendship, are good, no matter whether they be
desired or not.
3. Welfare consequentialism,
which identifies utility with the satisfaction of interests rather than mere
preferences.
Problem: it's hard to come up with a list of ‘true’ (vs. merely
perceived) interests.
Utilitarianism: John Stuart Mill
1) The basic
principle of Mill's Utilitarianism is the greatest happiness principle (PU): an
action is right insofar as it maximizes the good (Utility), which Mill
identifies with happiness.
NOTES:
2) Happiness is:
Note that since the maximization of pleasure is at
the root of PU, Utilitarians take into consideration not only persons but other
sentient creatures (non-human animals) as well.
3) "Proof" of PU
No strict proof can be given in issues of ultimate ends because it would
involve evaluating basic values, which cannot be done.
However, some evidence that general happiness (i.e., pleasure & absence of
pain) is the ultimate good can be given:
Problems:
4) The hedonistic
calculus follows the pattern of cost-benefit analysis (CBA), which involves 5
basic steps:
Problems:
Reply: M. distinguishes
o
the
morality of the action, which depends only on the consequences and not on the
agent’s intentions
o
the
morality of the agent, which depends on the intention of the agent and not on
the consequences of the action.
So, if I acted because I felt
duty-bound to maximize general happiness and strove to do it, then I am a moral
agent irrespective of whether my action is moral or not.
An
example of utilitarian decision: sending the flowers to the old lady instead of
buying the ticket for the soccer match.
Thought Questions:
·
From
a utilitarian point of view, was the US morally justified in dropping atomic
bombs on Japan?
·
Is
the death penalty morally justified?
·
Should
I keep a promise if breaking it would maximize happiness?
5) The sanctions of PU.
What is the motive for following PU?
·
External
sanctions:
o
human,
to the extent society is rational.
o
divine,
since God is good and wants our happiness.
6) Mill distinguishes two
types of moral duties:
1.
Imperfect
duties, the particular performance of which is left to our own decision, as in
the duty of charity
2.
Perfect
duties, virtues such that a correlative right
is possessed by person or persons, as in the duty to respect property, which is
associated to a right to property.
Justice is associated with perfect duties, and PU determines which rights are
possessed by individuals. For
Utilitarianism, rights are parasitic on general happiness. So, for Mill
one has a right only if society benefits from it. This may be sufficient
to guarantee certain rights, e.g., to security (otherwise vigilantism), to free
speech (society is better off with free market of ideas), property (more goods
to go around) etc. So, Mill can claim that certain acts are not just wrong
because they don't maximize utility, but unjust as well because they impinge on
one's right.
7) General problems with Utilitarianism. Some of the problems below overlap.
A) Distribution Justice:
PU
tells us to maximize happiness. But one can (perhaps surreptitiously)
maximize total utility irrespective of distributive justice, need or merit
e.g., by making few undeserving and already happy people fabulously happy at
the expense of many rather unhappy, deserving people. Conversely, PU
might require radical, and many would say unjust, redistribution of
property from the minority to the majority.
Replies:
·
Society
does not distribute happiness but goods (e.g., money) which generate happiness
in people who have them. But, the law of diminishing marginal utility
tells us that goods produce more happiness in those who have few of them than
in those who have many (if you give $ 1,000 to Bill Gates, he won't even
notice; if you give them to me, I'll be ecstatic). Hence, other things
being equal, people in need should be satisfied before people with no
need. S
·
Since
gaining desert involves disutility (e.g., work, stress etc.), other things
being equal, deserving people are capable of greater marginal utility than
non-deserving ones, and hence should be satisfied before
non-deserving ones.
·
The
need for stability and security in the planning of one's life would drastically limit
any radical redistribution of property to the majority.
·
We
want to give people incentives to do things that produce happiness, and this
may include appropriate rewards.
NOTE:
these are, however, contingent reasons; nothing in utilitarianism is essentially
against drastic redistribution of any sort.
B) The
end justifies the means:
Replies:
1. Paley’s distinction between particular and general consequences of
an action
2. Distinction between Act Utilitarianism and Rule Utilitarianism (not in Mill):
·
Act
Utilitarianism, which evaluates an individual act A on the basis of its
predicted actual consequences. Whether other people would also perform A
is relevant only to the extent that it is likely they would.
·
Rule
Utilitarianism, which evaluates an individual act A by appealing to a rule R,
and R on the basis of its predicted consequences if everyone were to follow
R.
NOTE: R here is not a mere rule of thumb, but an essential component of the
evaluation of A.
Problem: Do exceptions to rules (e.g., stealing if starving) make Rule
Utilitarianism degenerate into Act Utilitarianism?
C) Rights:
PU tells us to maximize general happiness. But happiness might be maximized by trampling on someone’s or some group's rights. This is very bad because the moral obligations involving rights are especially stringent. It’s true that Utilitarianism has a theory of rights, but many have questioned its power
Some controversial cases:
Thought Question: Could Paley help here? Rule Utilitarianism?
D) Replaceability
(impersonality).
Utilitarianism
seems to view people as vessels of pleasure and pain rather than as persons: as
long as utility is transferred from one subject to the other without spillage,
as it were, the utility level remains the same. This seems to be the
source of problems (A) and (B).
Reply: Impersonality guarantees impartiality, namely that each
individual is treated the same when it comes to happiness.
Duplication: Impersonality is not a necessary condition for
impartiality. Impartiality can be achieved otherwise, e.g., by analogues
of Rawls’s original position.
E) Integrity (B. Williams’ essay)
F) Supererogation:
There
is a traditional distinction among:
Utilitarianism seems to
collapse (1) and (3) into (2). Every act has some consequences, and hence
comes under the purview of PU.
Reply:
It may be the case that people are happier if morality doesn't mold every
aspect of their lives. If so, then
PU may demand that (1) and (3) not be collapsed into (2).