Abortion
Abortion (as humans are concerned) consists in deliberately
ending pregnancy. At present, this amounts to killing a fetus
either directly or by causing a miscarriage.
No part in the abortion debate thinks that abortion is per se a good
thing, and therefore nobody is pro-abortion (‘Hey, Mary, how about a nice
abortion today after a good cappuccino?’); nobody wants to see the number of
abortions increase. So calling
supporters of a woman’s right to choose ‘pro-abortion’ is misguided, to put it
charitably. (That a lot of people fall
for it does not make it less misguided.
If a view is misguided, company does not make is less misguided, just
more common). So, the issue is not
whether abortion is a good thing we want to have more of, but whether a
woman has a moral right to abort the fetus.
Since all
want to see the number of abortions diminish, an interesting issue is how to
achieve this common goal. As usual,
there is disagreement, the recipes going from more and better contraception and
sex education to ‘have sex only if you want a baby.’ We won’t go into this.
Here are
some basic facts about abortion in the US.
Note that 61% of abortions occur before 9 weeks and about 80% before 10
weeks.
Biologically
there are four main stages of an
unborn human: zygote (from conception to 4-5 days); blastocyst (from 5 days to implantation in the uterine wall- about
9 days); embryo (from implantation to first sign of brain waves—about
eight weeks); fetus (from about eight weeks to birth). Often, in
non-medical setting the term ‘fetus’ is used to cover all stages.
Some specifically religious
considerations
·
The
scholarly consensus is that the Bible has no direct injunction against
abortion. So, both those who say that on
biblical ground abortion is prohibited and those who say it’s permitted, have
to infer their conclusion. As usual, we get the battle of the Bible,
with different people reaching different conclusions by appealing to different
passages. The only thing that seems clear
is that the Bible by and large values women less than men and children from one
month to five years of age less than women; no mention is made of babies
younger than one month or fetuses (Leviticus 27: 1-7). Consistently, in terms of counting people
babies younger than a month are excluded (Numbers 3: 15-16).
·
In
agreement with this general devaluing, in early rabbinical Judaism a fetus is
not a full human being and therefore its killing is not murder. Today, in spite of differences in Jewish Law
abortion is permitted to save the life and health (physical or psychological) of
the woman. There is no consensus whether
abortion is permissible in the first trimester to avoid giving birth to a
severely malformed baby, or in the case of rape or incest. However, by and large the Jewish position is
pro-choice.
·
Historically,
by and large the Christian position has been that abortion in early pregnancy,
although sinful, does not amount to murder.
Much of the debate has been about hominization, namely, when the fetus
is ensouled. Traditionally, this was
tied to embryology, and the mainline view was that early abortion, up to
quickening, is permissible. Today, Christians are divided. For example, mainline European protestant
denominations allow abortion to preserve the life or health of the woman. After the 5th century, Catholics
did not consider early abortion as murder until 1869, when Pius IX stated that
abortion is homicide and forbidden in all
circumstances. Although this claim is
not declared an infallible pronouncement –it’s a proper subject of theological
discussion, it has been confirmed in 1930 and in 1974. However, the termination of the pregnancy is
permissible in some cases; for example, a woman suffering from an aggressive
uterine cancer may undergo chemotherapy that will result is miscarriage because
the miscarriage is foreseen but not intended and it is not the means by which
the cure is produced (This is an application of the doctrine of double effect).
Thought Question: should one consider
embryology in deciding when ensoulment takes place?
Thought Question: how about slippery slope
arguments, like: we cannot fix a precise point at which the fetus is ensouled,
and therefore we must say that it’s ensouled at conception? [Hint: how about being bald?]
More general considerations
Two issues are
typically discussed:
a) is the fetus a person?
b) if it is, how do we solve conflicting claims?
A) The status of the fetus.
1. An argument for the immorality of
abortion which immediately comes to mind is this:
i. the fetus is an innocent human being
ii. killing an innocent human being is very wrong because s/he has a right to life
iii. Hence, abortion is very
wrong
Problem:
Premise (ii) fails to distinguish between being genetically human and being a person. It is persons who have a right to life. Killing humans is very wrong insofar as they are persons. That is, belonging to the species Homo sapiens is not per se morally significant unless it is connected with being a person. It’s an open question whether a human fetus is a person or not.
2. When is a being a person? It is clear that one who is self-conscious and acts on the basis of one’s moral beliefs qualifies as a person (ask yourself when you would call a being from outer space a person). Obviously, any normal adult human being qualifies as a person under these criteria, and no fetus does. However, it is perhaps possible to relax the personhood criteria somewhat. Feinberg claims that five necessary and sufficient conditions are embedded in the commonsense notion of personhood:
NOTE: (1)-(4) are less
problematic than (5). Perhaps (1)-(4) are enough for personhood.
So, a being who actually has (1)-(5) is a person
and therefore has a right to life.
NOTES:
Thought
Question:
Does a newborn satisfy (1)-(5)? At what
point are (1)-(5) so relaxed as to be satisfied by some (many?) animals?
3. Proposed extensional equivalents of moral personhood.
Thought
Question:
does the zygote qualify?
Problem:
It seems that beings which
have (1)-(5) potentially are merely potential persons, and consequently
have at best merely potential rights. But a potential right is not a right any
more than a potential meal is a meal. A 9-year old citizen has a
potential right to vote, but we don't admit her in the voting booth.
Reply:
having (1)-(5) potentially confers not actual full rights, but actual
weak rights which grow stronger the closer the subject comes to having
(1)- (5).
Duplication: The argument moves from almost qualification to a right to
a weak version of the right, and the move is illicit. The day before
inauguration the would-be president has no right (not even a weak one) to
command the armed forces.
NOTES:
·
There’s
a lot of debate on this. Thought Question: What do you think?
·
Although
a potential right is no right at all, and hence not a weak right, pro-choicers
typically argue that the closer the subject is to having an actual right, the
more interest we should have in the preservation of the subject in the light of
the right it almost has. (Think of the
security around the president elect).
Thought
Question: if zygotes are persons, should we seriously engage in
avoiding natural miscarriages (about 65% of cases –we are lucky to be alive;
most of us don’t make it)? Should we monitor women of child bearing age to
make sure they don’t engage in behavior that may result in natural
miscarriage?
Thought
Question: By
some estimates, if we avoided natural miscarriages there would be about 15%
malformed babies instead of about 2%.
Would we have a moral duty to take care of them, given that we forced
them to be born?
4.
Suppose that the proposed extensions of personhood and rights beyond the actual
possession of (1)-(5) fail and that one should accept actual possession
of (1)-(5) as the criterion for personhood and rights. Then abortion is never murder.
Problems:
The requirement of actual possession of (1)-(5) seems too strong:
Thought Question: is this reply
satisfactory? Often people have very
strong intuitions about this.
B) The
problem of conflicting claims
The only thing that everybody agrees on, is that woman has full rights of
her own. So, if the fetus has right
of its own, then abortion involves a conflict of rights. There are two main cases here:
1. The fetus as the right to life in virtue of being a potential person
2. The fetus has the right to life in virtue of being an actual, full-fledged, person.
Suppose for the sake of argument that (1) it true. Then we are faced with two individuals, the fetus and the woman, a potential person and an actual person. If rights accrue to one in virtue of one’s personhood, the rights of the woman have precedence.
Problem: Presumably, rights are on a sliding scale in terms of importance. For example, my right to life is more important than your right to property. So, does ‘some’ right to life the fetus has trump the full right to property the woman has? How about her liberty? How about her ability to pursue happiness?
Thought Question: What do you think?
Suppose for the sake of argument that (2) is true. That is, assume, for argument's sake, that the fetus is a person. Then, we are faced with opposing rights of two full-fledged persons. In this case, there are three basic rights on which the right to have an abortion has been based:
1. Property rights over one's body.
There are several ways of presenting this point. The main problem is that property rights are
less important than the right to life of persons. Property rights cannot justify murder.
2. The
right to self defense
The intentional killing of a person seems justifiable in cases
of self-defense involving survival, maiming, rape, perhaps even severe
beating. But pregnancy and/or
having an unwanted child can bring severe harm to a woman (think of
cases of rape, much too many children, very difficult pregnancy).
Problem:
the standard cases of self-defense involve killing an aggressor; but the fetus
is not an aggressor (not even an innocent one).
Thought Question: is it justifiable
(though regrettable) to kill the innocent shield of a threat? (Thomson’s
case of the tank with the baby).
NOTE: Hence, the right to self-defense at most allows abortion only if a woman's life is at substantial risk. However, abortion to have a happy life or to improve one’s welfare is not justified because one cannot kill an innocent person in order to be happy.
3. The
right to bodily autonomy
In the case of Thomson's plugged-in-violinist, it would be supererogatory
to remain plugged. Hence, in cases of unwanted pregnancy, it would
be supererogatory, though not morally obligatory, to bring the fetus to term
(to remain plugged). The violinist has a right to life but not to my body,
Thomson claims.
Thought Question: is your intuition the
same as Thompson’s? What’s the problem
of appealing to intuitions?
Problem:
There's a disanalogy between abortion and the violinist case; the woman,
by voluntarily having sex, is often co-responsible for the
existence of the fetus. But voluntariness entails responsibility,
and therefore the woman's responsibility toward the fetus will be
proportional to the degree of voluntariness.
Thought Question: Can you think of
interesting cases? Rape? Failure of contraceptive? Being swept along in the passion of the
moment?
NOTE: At most, bodily autonomy guarantees only a limited right to abortion.
C. A Different Approach
Perhaps the preceding analysis has centered too much on the notion of right. Perhaps we should say that killing a fetus is wrong because it deprives it of a future that the person the fetus would become would enjoy. (This is Marquis’ FLO position; he claims that this is the reason why killing someone is wrong in general).
Note that this sort of consideration often comes up when discussing the alleged evil of death.
Problems:
‘Would enjoy’ needs clarification. Anybody can become almost anything in principle, but it’s very unlikely a mine slave will get a life she will enjoy. So, should we say ‘might reasonably expect to enjoy’? If so, there are two consequences:
1. The closer a fetus is to birth, the less likely that it will be damaged or die, and therefore the more wrong it is to kill it. This sounds good because it captures a very widespread intuition.
2. Suppose the fetus has very few chances of becoming a person with a life s/he’ll enjoy. Then it would be more permissible to abort it than a prospectively luckier fetus? Do we really want to say that a fetus in a miserable slum is less ‘valuable’ than one in a posh neighborhood?
3. Suppose that the woman, by having the baby, will severely diminish her chances of an enjoyable future and all but guarantee a miserable life for her newborn, while by aborting she’ll greatly increase hers. Would then abortion be justified?
Thought Question: What do you think? Does FLO suffer from impersonality, a bit like Utilitarianism is alleged to by some of its critics? More generally, can we really avoid talk of rights?
ROE v. WADE and other major
Supreme Court decisions
Roe v. Wade
A. The principals
The appellant was Jane Roe (a pseudonym), who challenged the constitutionality of Texas Statutes Articles 1191, 1192, 1193, 1194 and 1196 concerning abortion. Her lawyer argued that the interference of the State of Texas in Roe’s private life was:
The appellee was the State of Texas. It argued that:
B.
In Roe v. Wade, the Court addressed the Texas Statutes and
attempted to determine why these statutes had been passed, and whether there
were good reasons behind them consistent with the state interest in the police
powers. The Court came up with three possible reasons for the statutes:
Response: Even if this was the
purpose of the laws, today abortions performed with appropriate medical
supervision are safe.
C.
The argument of the Court
The argument of the Court rests on
the idea that there are three important interests at stake.
D. Conflicting interests and the stages of pregnancy
1. First trimester
Since abortions at this early stage are extremely safe, the state has no compelling interest to regulate beyond its normal interest in protecting health. Because of the nature of the fetus at this early stage, the State's interest in protecting potential life is also minimal. Consequently, these other interests are not sufficiently strong to interfere in the privacy and liberty of the woman.
2. Second trimester
Since abortions become more risky at this stage, the state's interest in regulating them is stronger. Hence, it can regulate, provided the regulation is reasonably related to the health of the woman. The state's interest in protecting potential human life is also stronger, since the potential human is closer to becoming an actual human person. However, that interest is not yet sufficiently strong to allow the state to interfere in the woman's privacy and liberty.
3. Third trimester
The woman's interest in privacy and liberty are as strong as before. However, once the fetus is viable, the Court believes that the State may choose to regulate, even prohibit, abortion, as long as the life and health of the mother are not threatened.
E. The decision of the Court
NOTES:
The decision
was 7-2, with justices White and Rehnquist writing an emphatic dissenting
opinion.
F. Further major
developments
Webster v. Reproductive
Health Services (1989)
Missouri placed restrictions on abortion by:
·
Banning
the use of public funds for abortion and abortion counseling unless the life of
the woman was in danger
·
Banning
abortions in public hospitals and clinics, unless the life of the woman was in
danger
·
Forbidding
public employees to assist in the performance of abortion, unless the life of the
woman was in danger.
In a 5-4 decision, the Supreme Court did not overturn the
law; however, it reaffirmed that provision limiting abortion in the second
trimester are unconstitutional.
Planned Parenthood v. Casey
(1992)
The Pennsylvania legislature amended its abortion control
law in 1988 and 1989. Among the new provisions, the law required:
·
Informed
consent and a 24 hour waiting period prior to the procedure.
·
The
demand that a minor seeking an abortion required the consent of one parent (the
law allows for a judicial bypass procedure).
·
The
demand that a married woman seeking an abortion had to indicate that she
notified her husband of her intention to abort the fetus.
In 5-to-4 decision, the Court reaffirmed Roe, but it upheld
most of the Pennsylvania provisions by imposing a new standard, namely, whether
a state abortion regulation has the purpose or effect of imposing an
"undue burden," which is defined as a "substantial obstacle in
the path of a woman seeking an abortion before the fetus attains viability."
Under this standard, the only provision to fail the undue-burden test was the
husband notification requirement.
Gonzales v. Carhart (2007)
In 2003, the Federal Government passed the Partial-Abortion
Act Ban, which prohibits a specific abortion procedure (intact dilation and
evacuation) in which the fetus is pulled out feet first and then killed by
crushing the skull to remove it.
Proponents argued that it’s a rare procedure amounting to killing a baby;
opponents argued that the ban also prohibits a common procedure, dilation and
curettage, and that it’s sometimes necessary to protect the life and health of
the woman.
In a 5-4 decision, the Court determined that the ban is
constitutional because consistent with Roe
and Planned Parenthood.
Ultrasound Laws
In recent years, in the USA about 20 states have adopted, or are considering adopting, laws that require a woman seeking abortion to undergo ultrasound procedures to give her the opportunity to observe the fetus and hear its heartbeat. (As an example of such laws, here is the ultrasound law in the state of Texas).
In Texas, the woman may decline the viewing and hearing but not the exam. Apart from particular cases such as rape or certified severe malformation of the fetus, she is required to listen to an explanation of the status of the fetus. Usually, in early pregnancy (before 9-10 weeks), the ultrasound examination is carried out by inserting an 11 inch wand made of hard plastic in the vagina of the woman, what’s medically called a transvaginal sonogram. 80% of abortions are carried out before the 10th week, which means that most women seeking an abortion will have to undergo this invasive procedure. No matter what the outcome, the woman has still a legal right to have an abortion; in other words, the examination is legally irrelevant to the right of the woman to have an abortion.
Notes:
· Such laws amount to the following: if you are a woman trying to exercise you legal right to have an abortion before 10 weeks, a right the Supreme Court has claimed to be rooted in the Constitution and which no State has any right to prohibit, you may be required to be vaginally penetrated whether your doctor believes this is medically necessary or not.
· Here’s the definition of rape according the World Health Organization: “physically forced or otherwise coerced penetration – even if slight – of the vulva or anus, using a penis, other body parts or an object.” (The definition is at p. 149 of this document, which also explains that threats about losing one’s job or getting a job count as coercion).
· Presumably, a woman who does not want to undergo a transvaginal sonogram will postpone abortion to about 12-13 weeks, by which time the ultrasound examination is typically carried out without the need of penetration of any body cavity.
Thought Question: how does the law sit with the idea that the later the abortion the more wrong it is?
Thought Question: Is the threat to prevent you from exercising a legal right unless…, amount to coercion? Note that a woman has no legal right to a job but the has a constitutionally based right to have an abortion. If so, does transvaginal sonogram in the law amount to state mandated rape? Is Texas a rape state? If so, what does this say about this country, its claims about freedom, and the status of women?