De Waal notes
De Waal: morally evolved
Two models of human beings: as
social by nature and as individualistically a-social by nature
Social contract theories and
the individualist model; even if taken hypothetically they distract us from the
biological reality of humans as "obligatorily gregarious."
homo economicus models in economics and the
social sciences.
Issues:
·
enlightened
self-interest (utility maximization) as prescriptive?
· Behavioral game theory
Veneer Theory: we are
"naturally" selfish; morality is a cultural overlay. Hence, morality
is, at most, a byproduct of adaptive traits.
Issues:
· Links to
original sin stories?
· Curbing of
the explanatory powers of evolution: it’s hard to see what evolutionary story
can lead from selfish subjects to prosocial and moral ones.
· Implicit
dualism: by adopting morality we create ourselves and, in a sense, transcend
nature. Hidden anti-naturalism?
Huxley, Kropotkin, Darwin,
Westermarck
Issues:
· Darwin
resorts to group selection. De Waal is skeptical,
maybe because of unit of selection
problems
· De Waal: no
need of group selection; kin selection and reciprocal altruism are sufficient
to get to morality. Are they?
The Russian Doll model: morality
as an outgrowth of animal sociality. The
‘bottom up’ construction of morality
Two different stages of
empathy:
1. Emotional contagion: having
same feeling as the other. This results
in personal distress, which produces helping behavior to relieve one’s own
distress
2. Empathy proper: being able
to "know" what the other is feeling.
This leads to sympathy: one feels sorry for the other without having the
same feelings as the other. Seems to
involve being able to put yourself in the other's shoes.
Empathy allows targeted helping
(observed in apes, dolphins and elephants) and consolation behavior (observed
only in hominoids). They may require
1.
the self-other
distinction,
2.
ToM.
More sophisticated behaviors
involve gratitude and a sense of fairness
· Gratitude requires time lag, memory, and the ability
to recognize benefactors. Note deWaal’s experiments with chimps involving
grooming followed by food sharing
· Capuchin monkeys’ sense of fairness, understood as
anger at not being treated according to a ‘sense of social regularity’, socially
based expectations. Note De Waal’s
distinction between this and human fairness, based on a principle, he says.
Humans are naturally parochial,
very sensitive to community concerns.
This makes morality restricted: its main problem is the expansion from
in-group to universality. This expansion depends on available resources.
Since parochialism is enhanced
by enmity towards outsiders, war and morality are linked: War served as
selection pressure for socialization.
Issue
As for Hume, moral sentiments are partial but social, not egoist. If
they were merely egoist, any sort of altruism would be hypocritical. By
contrast, one may hope that social sentiments can be expanded to include strangers
and other living creatures.
Morality is a ‘logical outgrowth’
of cooperative tendencies rooted not in rationality but in the passions. De
Waal presents some psychological evidence:
· Haidt on affect driven intuitions and moral automatism
· developmental psychology on very early and reliable
ontogeny of moral sentiments and capacities such as the spontaneous comforting
of others in babies
Continuist views of morality
have been overlooked because of the ‘Beethoven error’: the idea that a cruel
process (evolution) can't produce morality, just like it's hard to see that Beethoven's
messy apartment could be the site for his precise compositions. It’s a variety
of the process/product fallacy.
APPENDICES
Georgia’s ambushes,
anthropomorphism, anthropodenial, and the conflict between:
· cognitive parsimony (explain behavior by appealing to
the lowest possible mental capacities)
· evolutionary parsimony (if closely related species act
similarly, probably they have similar mental processes)
True, we shouldn't just project
human emotions and intentions onto animals, but the attribution to hominoids of
affective and cognitive abilities similar to ours is necessary if we want to
understand anything about them.
The asymmetry of the animal/human relation rules out the attribution of real rights to animals. Instead, towards them we should develop an ethic of care. In particular, all research on the great apes should be mutually beneficial and enjoyable.
COMMENTS
R. Wright
There are two types of
anthropomorphic language, emotional and cognitive. De Waal credits animals with too much
cognitive ability (planning, strategizing) when emotional regulation is
probably enough because
· many emotions have been designed by evolution as
proxies for strategic calculation favoring gene multiplication, and therefore
they are often effective
· they are presumably based in older parts of the brain
· one should adopt the principle of anthropomorphic parsimony: use only one of the
anthropomorphic languages if possible and if no evidence militates against it.
Wright distinguishes between
1.
Veneer theory,
which considers morality a purely cultural overlay grating against our true
nature, and has anti-naturalistic tones
2.
naturalistic
veneer theory: our moral impulses are rooted in our genes, that is, in ‘heavily
emotional’ intuitions, about kin, justice, etc.
He adopts (2) and not (1). He also claims that sometimes our genetically
based moral intuitions are lead astray by other genetically based intuitions,
for example when our justice intuitions become biased against our enemies and
in favor of friends.
C. Korsgaard
In
spite of being popular in the social sciences, the veneer theory is
unsatisfactory on several grounds:
· the principle of self-interest is
o
not proven to be
an effective principle of practical reason because nobody has been able to
establish its normativity.
o
actually not
followed, as we often fail to act on it by following fancy and ‘vagrant
inclinations’, as Butler says.
· The very concept of self-interest is not ‘well formed’
when it comes to social animals like humans because our own self-interest
cannot be set apart from that of others.
· Most of us don’t in fact have to struggle to act in a
moral manner. Only psychopaths have to restrain rampant self-interest.
· It’s ‘absurd’ to think that non-human animals can act
in their self-interest because:
o
This requires a
cognitive sophistication (grip on the future and ability to calculate) they
don’t have
o
Acting in
one’s best interest involves being
motivated by the abstract notion of one’s overall good. They don’t have
such type of motivation because they are wantons: they act on the
instinct/desire which is strongest at the moment.
Some animals are very similar
to us in being intelligent, curious, loving, bellicose as we are. However, there is a sharp discontinuity
between humans and other animals evidenced in
(1)
Our elaborate
cultures, historical memory, languages, art, literature, science, philosophy,
jokes, and our ability to make friends with members of other species
(2)
the fact that we
seem psychologically damaged, as Nietzsche and Freud hold, which suggests a
break with nature.
Although some animals are aware
of their goals and think about how to achieve them, only humans can choose them, namely, think whether they
are worth pursuing; by contrast, animals pursue their goals because they are
driven by affective states. That means they are determined, and have no freedom,
which can exist only in “normative self-government”. Choice presupposes reason, as distinct from intelligence,
namely a type of self-consciousness involving the consideration of grounds of action as grounds. It is this
epistemological stance that is unique to humans and makes the transition
between us and animals not merely a matter of degree but of kind.
P. Kitcher
Both veneer theory and its
polar opposite, that morality is already present in animals, are not held
today. More troublesome is the
‘Hume-Smith lure’, namely the idea that:
· Evolutionary theorists can show how sympathy and
psychological altruism could have evolved;
· Such sentiments are already present in animals
(Jackie, Krom, and the tires);
· morality can be obtained from them, Hume-Smith
fashion.
This is a lure because it
underestimates the complexity of psychological altruism, which can be
considered in terms of intensity, range,
extent, and skill, so that its representation would live in a four
dimensional space. We need to know what
type of altruism is relevant to morality
The basic difference between human
and animal altruism is that the former can be expanded to include all
humanity. Animals can’t universalize
their sentiments; we can, albeit with difficulty, by trying to adopt the
‘impartial spectator’ point of view.
Even chimps cannot do that because they are wantons.
Human morality probably arose
from our linguistic ability to share formulation and evaluation of plans, which
in turn led to the regulation of conduct in small groups. Group selection would
then favor the more smoothly run groups, and cultural evolution would favor the
expansion of morality.
P. Singer
Distinction between two
positions
1.
Human nature is inherently
social and the roots of morality are in the psychological traits we share
especially with primates
2.
All of morality
derives from our evolved nature as social animals
The first is true; the second
is false. De Waal at times seems to
accept both because the rejection of (2) implies some version of the veneer
theory; at other times he seems to accept only (1).
The basic difference between us
and animals is reason, which
· Does not have a purely social genesis because it also provides individual general advantages, e.g., in finding food.
· allows us to see that non-group members have interests
and concern similar to ours
· can be called into play against evolved instincts as
in the utilitarian answer to the trolley problem, as evidenced by brain scans.
The use of reason beyond
group-based social instincts is an essential part of morality so that some
aspect of morality is veneer, not reducible to the underlying structure.
Rights can be granted in
asymmetrical relations and can be partial (adults and babies, for example);
however, De Waal is right in focusing on our moral obligation towards animals
more than on animal rights. The basic
idea is equal consideration of interests,
which results in attributing special moral status to apes.
De Waal’s reply: The Tower of Morality
Morality is a group oriented phenomenon concerned with
the regulation of actions that could hurt
or help others; the rest is just “social convention”. Morality builds on, not against, our animal
nature.
The floating tower of morality
with concentric disks: self, family-clan, community, tribe-nation, humanity,
all life. They are listed in order of
importance: only when the needs of the more important are satisfied can those
of the others be satisfied if resources are available. (The denser the fluid, the more of the tower
emerges from it). This is not only factually true but also normatively right: we owe
special loyalty to the smaller disks.
There are three levels of
morality, where the higher ones cannot exist without the lower, and each is
associated with one of the following:
1.
Moral sentiments:
empathy, feeling of reciprocity
2.
Social pressure:
insisting that one behaves in ways that favor the group by means of punishment,
reward, and reputation-building.
3.
Judgment and
reasoning: asking why we think what we think; looking for coherent
justification for our choices
The first level we share with
some animals; the second we share with primates, although they tend to punish
bad behavior only when they are directly affected. The third is only human,
even though we never fully transcend ‘primate social motives’. So, the break with animals is found somewhere
in the second level.
Four different types of
altruism:
1.
Functional (biological): an action is altruist if it
produces a net loss for the agent and a net gain for the recipient
2.
Motivational: an action is altruist if it is the
result of concern for the recipient
3.
Intentional:
an action is altruist if the agent
intends to bring about a net gain for the recipient even at a net loss.
The first is very widespread in
nature, from bacteria to us. The second
is present from relatively large brained social animals to us; the third is
present in apes, us, and possibly some other animals.
A peculiar case of ‘altruism’
occurs when one engages in functional altruism out of enlightened selfishness;
this is very rare because it requires strategic choices.
Selfishness can be treated
analogously.