Providing an evaluation of the argument we are asked
to analyze (for the sake of brevity, let us call it argument “A”) is somewhat
complicated by the fact that argument A is given incompletely, since some
of its premises are clearly missing. Presumably, its general strategy consists
in trying to show that if all events are determined, people's attempts
at planning and affecting the future are unjustified, and consequently
that not all events are determined. More formally, argument A's broad structure
is as follows:
1) If all events are determined, people's planning in order to affect
the future is unjustified.
2) But people's planning in order to affect the future is justified.
3) Hence, not all events are determined.
One might object to the introduction of premise
(2) by arguing that it is not stated in argument A. However, brief reflection
shows that premise (2) is needed in order to infer conclusion (3) from
premise (1). Since as recast the argument is clearly valid (it's
an instance of modus tollens), the only issue remaining concerns
its soundness, namely, the truth of its premises. I shall argue that there
are problems with both of them. In fact I shall provide some grounds for
doubting the truth of premise (2); moreover, I shall show that premise
(1) does not sufficiently distinguish between standard determinism and
what I shall call ‘full fatalism”. As a result, one version of (1) 1 is
true but another is false. Consequently I shall conclude that, in spite
of its initial plausibility, while one version of argument involves full
fatalism and is perhaps sound, the other involving standard determinism
certainly is not.
Premise (2) claims that what is certainly
one of our most general and widespread form of activity, namely making
plans and executing them in order to affect the future, is justified. One
might try to argue that such behavior is so widespread that it must be
justified. But there is ground for doubting such a conclusion. Certainly
we know of many examples of behavior in which whole generations of people
engaged, and which were clearly unjustified. For example, consider the
social practices, which lasted many centuries, involved in the apprehension,
trial and burning of women thought to be witches. These practices were
based in part on the erroneous belief that witches exist. Similarly our
habit of planning for the future might be based on the false belief that
our actions can affect future events. Generally speaking, that certain
beliefs are widely held or certain practices widely followed does not entail
that they are justified. Moreover, the continuing success of
fortune tellers (just think e.g., of palm reading and horoscopes) seems
to indicate that many people base their plans for the future on the belief
that these charlatans can cast some light on how the future will be. Indeed,
it looks very much as if, for some at least, planning for the future is
inextricably and certainly at first sight irrationally connected with believing
that future events are already fixed. Consequently, appealing to the common
and allegedly justified habit of planning in order to conclude that the
future is not determined loses some of its initial plausibility.
In light of the previous considerations, one can reasonably claim that
the evidence for the truth of (2) is at best inconclusive. This is sufficient
to cast some doubt on the soundness of the whole argument.
While premise (2) is best characterized as doubtful,
premise (1) has much more severe problems. In order to see why, it is necessary
to analyze the view according to which events are determined. Broadly speaking
there are two main versions of it namely, standard determinism and full
fatalism.
According to standard determinism, every event,
including human choices, is determined by previous events. More precisely,
an event is seen as the result of initial conditions plus deterministic
laws, i.e., laws which, given the same initial conditions, guarantee that
the same outcome always occurs. For example consider a body at rest on
a ledge 10 meters from the ground, and suppose it begins to fall. If one
considers the laws governing the fall of bodies in such case, the velocity
the body will have at the moment of impact is fully determined and will
always be the same. 1 It is important to remark that according
to standard determinism, if the initial conditions or the governing laws
were different the outcome might, although it need not, be different. For
example, it the ledge were 12 meters from the ground, and the relevant
laws remained the same the velocity at impact would be different. 2
However, there is a particular version of the view
that events are determined which differs significantly, and as far as argument
A is concerned crucially, from standard determinism. The version in question
is full fatalism, which holds that events, or at least some of them, are
such that they could not be otherwise in the very strong sense that even
if the initial conditions or the laws of nature were different in whatever
way, the outcome would be the same. For example, if the body is fated to
hit the ground with a certain velocity, it will hit the ground with that
velocity no matter what the laws of falling bodies or its initial conditions
are. So, while according to standard determinism the initial of conditions
plus relevant laws have a bearing on the final outcome, according to full
fatalism they do not.
We are now in a position to see how a standard determinist
would analyze (1). Presumably, the evidence for (1) is as follows:
4) If all events are determined, then what will happen tomorrow is
already determined and nothing can change it.
5) Hence, what is determined to happen will happen.
6) Therefore, planning for the future is unjustified because the future
is already determined.
A standard determinist would question the transition from (5) to (6),
since for standard determinism what will happen tomorrow is partially dependent
on what one does today. Believing the contrary is accepting full fatalism.
A standard determinist would hold that what one does today is fully determined
and contributes in turn to determine what will happen tomorrow. Whether
I'll do well the course or not is already determined, but it certainly
does depend on whether I study or not. Consequently, argument A is powerless
against standard determinism. By contrast, argument A has some force
against full fatalism, for certainly if our present efforts at affecting
the future have no effect whatsoever, it is unjustified to act in order
to affect it. And if one assumes that we do act justifiably when we plan
for the future, fatalism must be false. However, such an assumption
might be denied by the full fatalist, and we have seen that the evidence
for its truth is far from conclusive.
The previous analysis shows that there are two distinct
versions of argument A. The first is obtained by interpreting the idea
that all events are determined in terms of standard determinism; the second
by interpreting it in terms of full fatalism. I have shown that the first
version is unsound and consequently does not prove that standard determinism
is wrong. By contrast the second version is sound, and consequently refutes
fatalism, if one assumes that our attempts at influencing the future are
not unjustified.
Notes
1. Neglecting air resistance and variations in the value of g for the sake of simplicity, the laws at play are:
s=v0t+1/2(gt2) and
v=v0+gt
Simple computation shows that the velocity v at the moment of impact
will be *sg that is, assuming g=9.8m/s2 ,14m/s.
2. In fact, it would be 15.3 m/s. This does not entail that an
outcome can be brought about only by the very same initial conditions and
the very fame governing laws that made it occur. For example, in the case
of the falling body, if the height of the ledge were 15 meters and the
value of g were 6.5m/s2, the final velocity would still be 14m/s.
Indeed, by playing around with v= *sg, one can see that there is an infinity
of initial conditions plus relevant laws which bring about the same outcome.