Introductory remarks
1) Morality occupies a central role in our lives because we make moral choices every day, some trivial, e.g., whether to tell a white lie, some serious, e.g., what position we should take on abortion, the death penalty, suicide & euthanasia, punishment, animal rights etc.
We typically appeal to morality when dealing with a variety of issues such as:
2) A judgment like “The Earth is round” is different in nature from one like “Murder is wrong”. For example, the latter involves a value judgment which we expect to result in an injunction, “Don’t murder”, towards which we should feel a duty. Some terminological distinctions may be useful:
NOTE:
Normative judgments typically result in injunctions
3) A moral judgment involves (1)-(2), and results in a
moral duty that must be fulfilled.
Non-compliance
·
deserves punishment
·
may give rise to justified anger
·
is expected to produce guilt in the transgressor
4)
The terms "ethics" and "morality" are often used
interchangeably. However, it may be helpful to introduce the following
distinction:
·
Morality
is a set of practices and beliefs that include normative criteria. To
be moral, one must strive to follow what morality prescribes. Being moral requires training of the intellect and of the emotions.
·
Ethics,
by contrast, is a theoretical discipline which studies morality.
NOTE: One needn't be moral to study morality any more than one needs to be a
believer to study theology: being an ethicist does not involve being moral.
·
This
course aims at teaching you ethics, namely at providing you with the intellectual tools to think about your moral
views. The result may be that you
change some of your moral views or that you reinforce them by finding new
justification for them.
5)
Ethics can be divided into different somewhat overlapping branches, depending
on the various ways to study morality:
1. Descriptive ethics, which tries
a. to describe the genesis of
morality. For example, is morality a
useful human invention, like the wheel?
Or is it the product of evolutionary pressure, like blood clotting? Or is it a divine gift to us?
b. to understand, and explain the
moral beliefs and practices, both general and particular, of a group (e.g., the
Huaorani, the white business community, SIUE
graduates, etc.)
2. Philosophical ethics , which has two overlapping
parts
a. metaethics, which tries to analyze basic
moral concepts (e.g., 'good' , 'right', 'duty', etc.), and to determine what
counts as a justification for a moral theory.
b. normative ethics, which tries to determine
which, if any, of the various moral frameworks is the correct one, what is
desirable (not merely desired), and when a person can be considered responsible
for some act. An interesting part of normative ethics is applied ethics,
which tries to determine the morally correct solution to a host of moral
problems in various areas of human endeavor and concern like medicine,
business, the environment, the judicial system, etc. The most concrete type of ethics is Casuistry, which studies the morality of
individual actions; this is often very hard because situations can be very
complex.
Note that the above areas overlap considerably. For example, determining the genesis of
morality has meta-ethical implications and is probably also relevant to
normative ethics. However, schematically
one could say the following:
Descriptive ethics: What percentage of Americans think the death penalty is
right? Have their views changed
lately? If so, how?
Normative (prescriptive) ethics: Should Americans
think that the death penalty is right?
That is, descriptive ethics tells us that they think thus and so, but
should they?
Applied ethics: What should Americans do about the death penalty? Or even, supposing Mr. Smith is guilty and
the death penalty justified, should he be executed, given his background, the
nature of his crime, etc.
Meta-ethics: What does 'right' mean?
That is, what should we mean when we say that the death penalty is
right? That the death penalty has the
property of being right as a tomato has that of being red? That we strongly approve of the death penalty,
so that when I say that the death penalty is right I really say “Up with the
death penalty!”? What?
6) Some very basic considerations
about addressing a moral issue.
i. How not to answer a normative ethical
question:
1.
At
most one learns how people do think, not how they ought to think. For example, religious intolerance is evil,
and the fact that it’s widely practiced makes it common, not less evil.
2.
Often
people are unreflective, swayed by prejudice and passions
3.
In
practice, we often witness a tyranny of the majority
1.
Before
justifiably appealing to authority we need to evaluate its
performance, i.e., know that it is, as it were, an authoritative authority. But
this requires that we already know what's right/wrong. Of course, we may have reasons
outside ethics to trust a certain authority. For example, we may trust the
minister because she is trustworthy in religious matters. However, her
theological ability need not transfer to moral matters. Historically, many
(perhaps all) religions and sects have supported horrible practices on the
basis of vies held authoritative theologians.
The same is true for political authority or familial authority (the
great leader knows best, and father knows best).
2.
Authorities
disagree
3. We should still know why an
authority is right
· By merely appealing to the law because morality and the law are not coextensive, as the existence of discriminatory laws shows.
· In a purely subjectivist mode, otherwise moral disagreement becomes impossible. If when Jim says “Homosexuality is wrong, for me” he merely means to report his subjective belief, and Joe says “Homosexuality is morally permissible, for me” in the same way, then Joe and Jim do not disagree at all. That is, there is a conflict between them as Jim may prevent Joe from adopting children or marrying his partner, but their moral statements don’t contradict each other because each is simply reporting one’s belief. In addition, Joe may agree with Jim that for Jim homosexuality is wrong, and Jim with Joe that for Joe homosexuality is permissible. Consequently, if pure subjectivism is correct, as long as Joe and Jim report their views correctly no moral disagreement is possible because they are both right. So, neither Jim nor Joe has a good reason to try to convince the other (each knows that the other is correct), and any discussion about who’s right and who’s wrong is pointless. The result is that morality fails to provide a ground on which to resolve conflicts. Hence, when one says “I believe that homosexuality is permissible” in a moral discussion he should not merely report one’s subjective belief; rather, one should be implicitly saying that others should also believe that homosexuality is permissible, otherwise one has moved the discussion to psychology or sociology
ii. What to look for in an answer to a
normative ethical question:
.